Painful as it doubtlessly is to be caught within a decaying research program some profit may be gained by reflecting on the situation, refusing an immediate shift to some more promising enterprise. There is a powerful tendency to set up and conform to international standards and philosophical reaction is instinctively defined in contraposition to the path progress is taking. We do, however, at the same time know better than that.Reverse movements are more adequately regarded as components of a multiple interplay of possible directions. There cannot, in my eyes, be any doubt about the blatant insufficiency of most neo-conservative attempts to deal with the complexities of the present situation. But employing the by now outworn scientific jargon of the original Vienna Circle is just as ill-conceived. If this is conceded the problem can tentatively be approached in a new way, allowing a legitimate place for the anxieties expressed by nostalgic schemes. By acknowledging that its own foundations rest on certain exclusions analytic philosophy has begun to respond to the challenge of contemporary thought. It was E.Heintel's view that only within the framework of his Fundamentalphilosophie analytic philosophy can be ,,more ... than the self-contained game of an arrogant and more or less esoterical sect. Such obvious blunders make it temptingly easy to turn the table on him and brand him a diehard sectarian himself. But this would amount to a continuation of this increasingly pointless game of name-calling. I am not driving at a compromise-solution either. Dialectical relationships between progress and reaction, modernity and post-modernism etc. seem much too simple to allow any confidence in long term judgement. What we are called upon is to search for new methods of making sense of the asynchronicity increasingly obvious behind the veneer of one common standard of development. If this sounds like easy relativism my answer is that facing relativity and not losing all of one's historically valid criteria is just the kind of hard work philosophy is called upon to perform.
How do our previous considerations touch upon these issues? Viennese philosophy seems to be caught between bye-gone glory and present malaise. The first thing to notice about this is that this state is neither recent nor specific to philosophy but rather a mark of 20th-century Austrian culture generally. As B.McGuinness remarks on the subversive effect of one of Karl Kraus' pieces ,,There is something Austrian about the fact that this bitter satire on the official propaganda was commonly carried by officers at the front, while British officers were satisfied with broadsheets reprinting pieces by Dickens, Macaulay, Shakespeare, and Scott. The Austrians were called upon to show courage without confidence in the value, let alone the success, of their cause.'' It would be short-sighted to regard this only as a loser's stoicism. The paradoxical logic of the saying ,,You do not have any chance - use it'' falls outside the scope of ordinary success-stories but carries a certain conviction (and even efficiency) nevertheless. The ambivalence of wanting to promote something that is beyond promotion is a feature of self-consciously being out of step with the general drift of political and economic affairs. And this is perhaps the best one can do in an environment that is rapidly destroying the familiar conditions of life. J.Nestroy, F.Grillparzer, K.Kraus, R.Musil and the later Wittgenstein are examples of this attitude, Herzmanovsy-Orlando, Th.Bernhard and P.Handke being more recent practitioners of this art. In order to appreciate their work one must be prepared to accept the progressive force of regressive phantasies. Inability to transform a given set of cultural dispositions into an easily applicable program for contemporary use is not in itself an indication of failure, neither is it restricted to a few hold-outs of unenlightened provincials. There is no guarantee that internationalism is always on the right track. Stepping out of the grip of a certain view of history allows one to regard inflexibility and even outright resistance to change as mark of an excessive demand made on an established way of life. I hasten to add that it does not follow that endangered pockets of resistance should be conserved by any means. Turning old habits into museum-pieces is no solution to the problem. My point is rather that the present state of philosophy demands that we pay attention not only to the unquestionable success-story of analytic philosophy but also to its hidden background and to the abortive attempts to protect oneself against it. Including the losers in one's historical narratives should not be restricted to cases of their belonging to the appropriate persuasion.
Another way to approach the same issue is to consider it within the framework of center and periphery F.Wimmer has proposed to apply to the description of 19th-century Austrian philosophy as well as to contemporary philosophy in Third World countries. His comparison does not only bring out diachronic structural similarities between areas not occupying a central position in a given hegemonical setting, it also serves to remind us of the problematic nature of this setting itself. The course I have been tracing in this paper can be compared to the emergence of a developing country into the status of the most developed ones, followed by a relapse into renewed dependency. If it is conceded that in philosophy and in the study of international relations likewise simplistic notions about the unidirectionality and linearity of progress are no longer feasible the perplexity arising from belonging to a marginal tradition is in itself a possible starting point. It is, as I have tried to indicate, not just a matter of polemics between quarreling academics, but an opportunity to devise a new attitude towards deeply entrenched patterns of cultural hegemony established during the post-war years.
It happens that the development of Anglo-American analytic philosophy is approaching closure just as the political and economical predominance of the US is in decline. Revived in Paris, Todtnauberg is very much in fashion again, no occasion to be particularly confident in the reign of Reason in History. But this is precisely the lesson to learn from the backward attempts to reinstall philosophia perennis where it was most fiercely attacked: retreating into metaphysics is not just a helplessly defensive move of a group of philosophers surpassed by modern times. It is -at the same time - an indication of the limits of a linear conception of history. In the context of his investigations on marginalized groups F.Wimmer coins the pertinent slogan of the need to reveal the ,,exoticism of majorities''. To proceed along these lines is to ask what has been endangered by their unquestionable and hence unquestioned dominance. If this century's philosophical geography is to overcome its own centralistic tendencies the ill-fated double of the Vienna Circle , the Vienna Roundabout, might serve as a place of transfer.